Inner perceptions are
separated from each other as distant enclosures within a single, continuous, curving,
visual surface.
Deleuze further describes the perspectivism associated with Leibniz as the
unfurling of divergent series in the same world, the creation and subjective production
of novelty in the objective world, the "emancipation of dissonance," and the liberation of
the "true quanta" of private subjectivity (The Fold 79-82). The multiplicity of
interconnected forces admits no stable entities, but only dynamic quanta, and must
therefore be understood in terms of multitudinous identities.
In Leibniz's metaphysics of monads, monadic selves are possibilities that are
actualized in composite substances, perceived qualities, colors, material things, or other
figures and extended phenomena. Reasoning monads are correlative to reflexive
objects, similar to Whitehead's thought, where thinking prehensions relate to
eternal objects. Ontological configurations, figures, things and qualities are permanent
forms that are reflected and actualized in monadic selves, but even their composite
substances are realized in flux and in a state of identity shift.
Paralleling Whitehead's ontology, monadic entities are fluvia,
endlessly being altered, forever entering and leaving variable components in
movement. Reflexive objects are weightless, because they are pure possibilities
that are realized in permanent flux, and pure virtualities that are actualized in
individual, thinking prehensions. Discord, irruption and irreconcilable dissonance are
resolved in a sense of polytonality, unresolved accord, and continuous, but
noncontiguous series of perceptions across a visual surface. The perpetual
motion and transformation of the abstract, visual surface forever conditions both
perceptions and thought.
The Influence of Whitehead and conceptual possibilities
Whitehead's ontology, as schematized in Process and Reality and
related, supplemental writings, extends the center of perceptual experience beyond the
self-organizing Kantian subject to the relational, pluralistic field of things in themselves.
Avoiding the "transcendental idealism" of post-Kantian thinkers, Whitehead puts forth a
framework that locates the object of experience within the objective conditions of the
world, in a realist system of "objective constructivism."
Perceptual experience involves the presentation of autonomous, external
objects or events as efficacious elements in subjective experience. Whitehead writes
that the actual elements perceived by our senses are in themselves the elements of a
"common world." The world of complex things is "transcended" by our thought, but the
things experienced and the thinking subject enter into worldly relationships on equal
terms (Process 88). In preserving the form of subjectivity in the general nature of
things, Whitehead is able to preserve the structural features of self-construction as an
ingredient in the nature of things, while avoiding the pitfalls of idealist and pan-psychist
thought.
In the act of synthesis and self-construction, every event stands at the center
of orientation for its objectively inherited environment. It functions as a self-organizing
perspective and a valuative reflection of the objective relations it inherits (Whitehead
210). For Whitehead, events are synthetic, relational entities and conjunctive moments
of antecedent, contemporary, and consequent relations between things in a
structure of subjective, or "tensed" time. Events also stand as primary "elements" or
"realities" to which other modes of being must be related: Whitehead suggests that both
events and objects may move beyond the conditions of past and present in a process
of contingent creation, toward a novel, indeterminate, open-ended future. Events
become the material forms of reality that capture the distinction, the liminal qualities,
between the possible (virtual) and the relationally situated (actual). Objects represent
the conceptual possibilities drawn from the pool of potential realities.
The present, prehending event is therefore a novel expression of
some qualities and properties inherited from past occurrances. Whitehead's
perspectivism becomes a vehicle for Deleuze to avoid a static, monistic universe devoid
of unrealized possibilities. It support Deleuze's notion that thought is wider, more
encompassing, and more divergent than finite actuality in its capacity to create
Leibnizian contingent futures and points of view. Thought takes place within the realm
of perverse reflections.
Concluding thoughts
In a concise and direct manner, Deleuze remarks that the neo-Baroque in
both form and thought represents the most forthright attempt to reconfigure classical
reasoning by dividing divergences into as many worlds as possible, and then creating
infinite, numerous borders, variable configurations, interactions, and captures between
worlds. Multiple perspectives are not contained in isolated self-enclosures, but are held
in innumerable sets of brackets and captures, and inflected in manifold twists of
curvature and point of view across a mobile, visual surface.
By way of some final thoughts, Deleuze's reading of aesthetics attempts to
make some connections between sensuous, multiple views of the world and abstract,
fluid algorithms of thought that are grasped visually and aesthetically. The effects of
the ideas deriving from hyperbolic and non-Euclidean geometries continues to have an
impact on the contemporary arts and poetries, digital design, and aesthetic theories of
perspective. In his depiction of multiple realities bracketed within monadic selves, of
reflexive, weightless bodies in perpetual displacement and shift, Deleuze discloses a
futurism containing an infinity of swarming parts and perceptions in quasi-liquid form
and curvilinear motion. His futuristic ideas lend credence to the realization of alternate,
perspectives on the contemporary arts, and between the blurred boundaries of the
virtual and actual.
Notes:
1. Beltrami provided the formula for a true hyperbolic plane, infinite in all directions.
Hyperbolic geometries create asymptotic geodesics that tend to tangency at infinity: Beltrami's projective
model of the hyperbolic plane distorts angles as well as lengths; surfaces can be mapped onto planes in
such a way that their geodesics, planetlike surfaces of constant negative curvature in ordinary space, were
flattened out to infinity. See David Hilbert and Stephan Cohn-Vossen, Geometry and the
Imagination (Providence: AMS Chelsea Publishing, 1991), 1-11. (back)
2. The signatures of the 1917 manifesto published in the Dutch journal De Stijl set forth a plan
of collaboration to create new conceptions of art based on emerging theories of time and space. The De
Stijl artists advocated the "neoplastic" aspect of art that follows the mathematical-artistic trend of a
geometric space in other than three dimensions. See Georges Vantongerloo, Paintings, Sculptures,
Reflections (New York: Wittenborn, Schultz, 1948), 38-39. (back)
3. Linda Henderson, The Fourth Dimension and non-Euclidean Geometry in Modern Art
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983), 339-340. (back)
4. See Marcos Novak, "Liquid Architectures in Cyberspace," in Michael Benedikt, ed.,
Cyberspace: First Steps (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), 225-54, and N. Katherine Hayles, "The
Condition of Virtuality," in Peter Lunenfeld, ed., The Digital Dialectic: Essays on New Media
(Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1999), 58-95. (back)
5. See Brian Massumi, "Introduction: Like a Thought" in Brian Massumi, ed., A Shock to thought:
Expression after Deleuze and Guattari (New York: Routledge, 2002), xxii-xxiii. (back)
6. In The Fold, the art of paper folding, a semi-fluid origami, becomes the model for both the
plastic arts and the sciences of matter. Following Leibniz, Deleuze affirms that curvature affects all
materials (metal, paper, fabrics, water, living tissue, the brain), because it determines and materializes
form. Curving materials become "expressive matter" with different scales, speeds, and vectors of force.
Since folding and the chiaroscuro effect are Baroque traits, pleating surfaces of color can be said to
resemble the overlaying folds and depths (crevices) of fabric or paper. The neo-Baroque is an "operative
function" or "trait" which endlessly produces curvy folds, then twisting, turning, and pushing them into
infinity, fold over fold, one on the other (3, 34). (back)
7. The study of algebraic curves, equally useful for formalism and the plastic arts, was extended by
abstract algebra and remains inseparable from geometric ideas. Deleuze discusses how Leibniz posits
the idea of families of curves depending on differential parameters (The Fold 18-19). (back)
8. See David Levin, Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1993), 73. (back)
9. Leibniz defines extension (extensio) as continuous repetition of the situs, position, or point of view:
Extension is not an attribute of point of view, but an attribute of space (spatium) and the order of distances
between points of view that permits repetition and continuity between related perspectives. (back)
Works Cited:
Benedikt, Michael, ed. Cyberspace: First Steps. Cambridge: MIT Press,
1991.
Bergson, Henri. Duration and Simultaneity, with Reference to Einstein's
Theory. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965.
Crary, Jonathan. Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the
Nineteenth Century. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990.
Crowther, Paul. The Language of Twentieth Century Art: A Conceptual
History. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997.
Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition. New York: Columbia University
Press, 1994.
- - - . The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque. Trans. Tom Conley. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1993.
- - - . Negotiations: 1972-1990. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.
Deleuze, Gilles and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1987.
Glazier, Loss. "(Go)fish." SUNY. 1998. http://epc.buffalo.edu/authors/glazier
Hardt, Michael. Gilles Deleuze: An Apprenticeship in Philosophy. London:
UCL Press, 1993.
Harris, Joe. Algebraic Geometry. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1992.
Henderson, Linda. The Fourth Dimension and non-Euclidean Geometry in
Modern Art. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983.
Hilbert, David and Stephan Cohn-Vossen. Geometry and the Imagination.
Providence: AMS Chelsea Publishing, 1991.
Krauss, Rosalind. The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist
Myths. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996.
Lang, Serge. Introduction to Complex Hyperbolic Surfaces. New York:
Springer-Verlag, 1987.
Lee, Gicheal. "Typorganism: Interactive, Kinetic Typography." New York University. 2001. http://www.typorganism.com.
Levin, David. Modernity and the Hegemony of Vision. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1993.
Lunenfeld, Peter, ed. The Digital Dialectic: Essays on New Media.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999.
Massumi, Brian. Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation.
Durham: Duke University Press, 2002.
Massumi, Brian, ed. A Shock to Thought: Expression after Deleuze and
Guattari. New York: Routledge, 2002.
Mondrian, Piet. The New Art, The New Life. Boston: G. K. Hall & Company,
1986.
Perloff, Marjorie. Radical Artifice: Writing Poetries in the Age of Media.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.
Serres, Michel. Le Systeme de Leibniz et ses Modèles Mathématiques.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1968.
Stephans, Brian Kim. "The Dreamlife of Letters." Lume 2 (2001): http://epc.buffalo.edu/ezines/lume
Vantongerloo, Georges. Paintings, Sculptures, Reflections. New York:
Wittenborn, Schultz, 1948.
van Doesberg, Theo. Principles of Neo-Plastic Art. New York: New York
Graphic Society, 1966.
Whitehead, Alfred. Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press, 1978.
Zervos, Kominos. "Life, A Navigation." SUNY UbuWeb Contemporary Arts. 2002. http://www.ubu.com/contemp_frames.html.
Citation
Format:
Kafala, Ted. "Deleuze's Aesthetics: Curvature and
Perspectivism." Enculturation 4.2 (Fall 2002):
http://enculturation.net/4_2/kafala.html
Contact
Information:
Ted Kafala, University of Cincinnati
Email: kafalat@email.uc.edu
Home Page: